Part #2

In Section VI of [the last essay], I adopted

---

1 Compare Professor MacLennan's admirable _Auseinandersetzung_ with Mr. Bradley, in _The_Journal_of_Philosophy,_Psychology_and_ _Scientific_Methods_, vol. I, [1904], pp. 403 ff., especially pp. 405-407.

101

in a general way the common-sense belief that

one and the same world is cognized by our

different minds; but I left undiscussed the

dialectical arguments which maintain that

this is logically absurd. The usual reason

given for its being absurd is that it assumes

one object (to wit, the world) to stand in two

relations at once; to my mind, namely, and

again to yours; whereas a term taken in a

second relation can not logically be the same

term which it was at first.

I have heard this reason urged so often in

discussing with absolutists, and it would destroy

my radical empiricism so utterly, if it

were valid, that I am bound to give it an attentive

ear, and seriously to search its strength.

For instance, let the matter in dispute be

term M, asserted to be on the one hand related

to L, and on the other to N; and let the two

cases of relation be symbolized by L-M and

M-N respectively. When, now, I assume

that the experience may immediately come

and be given in the shape L-M-N, with

no trace of doubling or internal fission in the

102

M, I am told that this is all a popular delusion;

that L-M-N logically means two different

experiences, L-M and M-N, namely;

and that although the Absolute may, and indeed

must, from its superior point of view,

read its own kind of unity into M's two editions,

yet as elements in finite experience the

two M's lie irretrievably asunder, and the

world between them is broken and unbridged.

In arguing this dialectic thesis, one must

avoid slipping from the logical into the physical

point of view. It would be easy, in taking

a concrete example to fix one's ideas by, to

choose one in which the letter M should stand

for a collective noun of some sort, which noun,

being related to L by one of its parts and to

N by another, would inwardly be two things

when it stood outwardly in both relations.

Thus, one might say: 'David Hume, who

weighed so many stone by his body, influences

posterity by his doctrine.' The body and the

doctrine are two things, between which our

finite minds can discover no real sameness,

though the same never covers both of them.

103

And then, one might continue: 'Only an Absolute

is capable of uniting such a non-identity.'

We must, I say, avoid this sort of example, for

the dialectic insight, if true at all, must apply

to terms and relations universally. It must be

true of abstract units as well as of nouns collective;

and if we prove it by concrete examples

we must take the simplest, so as to avoid

irrelevant material suggestions.

Taken thus in all its generality, the absolutist

contention seems to use as its major

premise Hume's notion 'that all our distinct

perceptions are distinct existences, and that

the mind never perceives any real connexion

among distinct existences.'(1) Undoubtedly,

since we use two phrases in talking first about

'M's relation to L' and then about 'M's relation

to N,' we must be having, or must have

had, two distinct perceptions; -- and the rest

would then seem to follow duly. But the starting-

point of the reasoning here seems to be the

fact of the two _phrases_; and this suggests that

---

1 [Hume: _Treatise_of_Human_Nature_, Appendix, Selby-Bigge's edition, p. 636.]

104

the argument may be merely verbal. Can it be

that the whole dialectic consists in attributing

to the experience talked-about a constitution

similar to that of the language in which we describe

it? Must we assert the objective doubleness

of the M merely because we have to name

it twice over when we name its two relations?

Candidly, I can think of no other reason

than this for the dialectic conclusion;(1) for, if

we think, not of our words, but of any simple

concrete matter which they may be held to

signify, the experience itself belies the paradox

asserted. We use indeed two separate concepts

in analyzing our object, but we know them all

the while to be but substitutional, and that the

M in L-M and the M in M-N _mean_ (i.e.,

are capable of leading to and terminating in)

one self-same piece, M, of sensible experience.

This persistent identity of certain units (or

emphases, or points, or objects, or members --

call them what you will) of the experience-

continuum, is just one of those conjunctive

---

1 Technically, it seems classable as a 'fallacy of composition.' A duality, predicable of the two wholes, L-M and M-N, is

forthwith predicated of one of their parts, M.

105

features of it, on which I am obliged to insist

so emphatically.(1) For samenesses are parts of

experience's indefeasible structure. When I

hear a bell-stroke and, as life flows on, its after

image dies away, I still hark back to it as 'that

same bell-stroke.' When I see a thing M, with

L to the left of it and N to the right of it, I see

it _as_ one M; and if you tell me I have had

to 'take' it twice, I reply that if I 'took' it a

thousand times I should still _see_it as a unity.(2)

Its unity is aboriginal, just as the multiplicity

of my successive takings is aboriginal. It

comes unbroken as _that_ M, as a singular which

I encounter; they come broken, as _those_ takings,

as my plurality of operations. The unity

and the separateness are strictly co-ordinate. I

do not easily fathom why my opponents should

find the separateness so much more easily understandable

that they must needs infect the

whole of finite experience with it, and relegate

---

1 See above, pp. 42 ff.

2 I may perhaps refer here to my _Principles_of_Psychology, vol. I, pp. 459 ff. It really seems 'weird' to have to argue (as I am forced now to do) for the notion that it is one sheet of paper (with its two surfaces and all that lies between) which is both under my pen and on the table while I write -- the 'claim' that it is two sheets seems so brazen. Yet I sometimes suspect the absolutists of sincerity!

106

the unity (now taken as a bare postulate and

no longer as a thing positively perceivable) to

the region of the Absolute's mysteries. I do

not easily fathom this, I say, for the said opponents

are above mere verbal quibbling; yet all

that I can catch in their talk is the substitution

of what is true of certain words for what is

true of what they signify. They stay with the

words, -- not returning to the stream of life

whence all the meaning of them came, and

which is always ready to reabsorb them.

IV

For aught this argument proves, then, we

may continue to believe that one thing can be

known by many knowers. But the denial of

one thing in many relations is but one application

of a still profounder dialectic difficulty.

Man can't be good, said the sophist, for man is

_man_ and _good_ is good; and Hegel(1) and Herbart

in their day, more recently A. Spir,(2) and most

---

1 [For the author's criticism of Hegel's view of relations, cf. _Will_to_Believe_, pp. 278-279, ED.]

2 [Cf. A. Spir: _Denken_und_Wirklichkeit_, part I, bk. III, ch. IV (containing also account of Herbart). ED.]

107

recently and elaborately of all, Mr. Bradley,

informs us that a term can logically only be

a punctiform unit, and that not one of the

conjunctive relations between things, which

experience seems to yield, is rationally possible.

Of course, if true, this cuts off radical empiricism

without even a shilling. Radical empiricism

takes conjunctive relations at their face

value, holding them to be as real as the terms

united by them.(1) The world it represents as a

collection, some parts of which are conjunctively

and others disjunctively related. Two

parts, themselves disjoined, may nevertheless

hang together by intermediaries with which

they are severally connected, and the whole

world eventually may hang together similarly,

inasmuch as _some_ path of conjunctive transition

by which to pass from one of its parts

to another may always be discernible. Such

determinately various hanging-together may

be called _concatenated_ union, to distinguish it

from the 'through-and-through' type of union,

---

1 [See above, pp. 42, 49.]

108

'each in all and all in each' (union of _total_

_conflux_, as one might call it), which monistic

systems hold to obtain when things are taken

in their absolute reality. In a concatenated

world a partial conflux often is experienced.

Our concepts and our sensations are confluent;

successive states of the same ego, and feelings

of the same body are confluent. Where the

experience is not of conflux, it may be of

conterminousness (things with but one thing

between); or of contiguousness (nothing between);

or of likeness; or of nearness; or of

simultaneousness; or of in-ness; or of on-ness;

or of for-ness; or of simple with-ness; or even of

mere and-ness, which last relation would make

of however disjointed a world otherwise, at any

rate for that occasion a universe 'of discourse.'

Now Mr. Bradley tells us that none of these

relations, as we actually experience them, can

possibly be real.(1) My next duty, accordingly,

---

1 Here again the reader must beware of slipping from logical into phenomenal considerations. It may well be that we _attribute_ a certain relation falsely, because the circumstances of the case, being complex, have deceived us. At a railway station we may take our own train, and not the one that fills our window, to be moving. We here put motion in the wrong place in the world, but in its original place the motion is a part of reality. What Mr. Bradley means is nothing like this, but rather that such things as motion are nowhere real, and that, even in their aboriginal and empirically incorrigible seats, relations are impossible of comprehension.

109

must be to rescue radical empiricism from Mr.

Bradley. Fortunately, as it seems to me, his

general contention, that the very notion of relation

is unthinkable clearly, has been successfully

met by many critics.(1)

It is a burden to the flesh, and an injustice

both to readers and to the previous writers, to

repeat good arguments already printed. So, in

noticing Mr. Bradley, I will confine myself to

the interests of radical empiricism solely.

V

The first duty of radical empiricism, taking

given conjunctions at their face-value, is to

class some of them as more intimate and some

as more external. When two terms are _similar_,

their very natures enter into the relation.

---

1 Particularly so by Andrew Seth Pringle-Pattison, in his _Man_and_ _the_Cosmos_; by L.T. Hobhouse, in chapter XII ("The Validity of Judgement") of his _Theory_of_Knowledge_; and by F.C.S. Schiller, in his _Humanism_, essay XI. Other fatal reviews (in my opinion) are Hodder's, in the _Psychological_Review_, vol. I [1894], p. 307; Stout's in the _Proceedings_of_the_Aristotelian_Society, 1901-2, p.1; and MacLennan's in [_The_Journal_of_Philosophy,_Psychology_and_Scientific_Methods_, vol. I, 1904, p. 403].

110

Being _what_ they are, no matter where or when,

the likeness never can be denied, if asserted.

It continues predictable as long as the terms

continue. Other relations, the _where_ and the

_when_, for example, seems adventitious. The

sheet of paper may be 'off' or 'on' the table,

for example; and in either case the relation

involves only the outside of its terms. Having

an outside, both of them, they contribute by it

to the relation. It is external: the term's inner

nature is irrelevant to it. Any book, any table,

may fall into the relation, which is created _pro_

_hac_vice_, not by their existence, but by their

causal situation. It is just because so many of

the conjunctions of experience seem so external

that a philosophy of pure experience must tend

to pluralism in its ontology. So far as things

have space-relations, for example, we are free

to imagine them with different origins even. If

they could get to _be_, and get into space at all,

then they may have done so separately. Once

there, however, they are _additives_ to one another,

and, with no prejudice to their natures,

all sorts of space-relations may supervene between

111

them. The question of how things could

come to be anyhow, is wholly different from

the question what their relations, once the

being accomplished, may consist in.

Mr. Bradley now affirms that such external

relations as the space-relations which we here

talk of must hold of entirely different subjects

from those of which the absence of such relations

might a moment previously have been

plausibly asserted. Not only is the _situation_

different when the book is on the table, but

the _book_itself_ is different as a book, from what

it was when it was off the table.(1) He admits

that "such external relations seem possible

and even existing. . . . That you do not alter

what you compare or rearrange in space seems

to common sense quite obvious, and that on

---

1 Once more, don't slip from logical into physical situations. Of course, if the table be wet, it will moisten the book, or if it be slight enough and the book be heavy enough, the book will break it down. But such collateral phenomena are not the point at issue. The point is whether the successive relations 'on' and 'not-on' can rationally (not physically) hold of the same constant terms, abstractly taken. Professor A.E. Taylor drops from logical into material considerations when he instances color-contrast as a proof that A, 'as contra-distinguished from B, is not the same thing as mere A not in any way affected' (_Elements_of_Metaphysics_, p. 145). Note the substitution, for 'related' of the word 'affected,' which begs the whole question.

112

the other side there are as obvious difficulties

does not occur to common sense at all. And I

will begin by pointing out these difficulties. . . .

There is a relation in the result, and this relation,

we hear, is to make no difference in its

terms. But, if so, to what does it make a difference?

[_Does_n't_it_make_a_difference_to_us_on-_

_lookers,_at_least?_] and what is the meaning and

sense of qualifying the terms by it? [_Surely_the_

_meaning_is_to_tell_the_truth_about_their_relative_

_position_.1] If, in short, it is external to the terms,

how can it possibly be true _of_ them? [_Is_it_the_

_'intimacy'_suggested_by_the_little_word_'of,'_here,_

_which_I_have_understood,_that_is_the_root_of_Mr._

_Bradley's_trouble?] . . . If the terms from their

inner nature do not enter into the relation,

then, so far as they are concerned, they seem

related for no reason at all. . . . Things are spatially

related, first in one way, and then become

related in another way, and yet in no

way themselves are altered; for the relations,

it is said, are but external. But I reply that, if

----

1 But "is there any sense," asks Mr. Bradley, peevishly, on p. 579, "and if so, what sense in truth that is only outside and 'about' things?" Surely such a question may be left unanswered.

113

so, I can not _understand_ the leaving by the

terms of one set of relations and their adoption

of another fresh set. The process and its

result to the terms, if they contribute nothing

to it [_Surely_they_contribute_to_it_all_there_is_

_'of'_it!_] seem irrational throughout. [_If_'irrational'_ _here_means_simply_'non-rational,'_or_non-_

_deducible_from_the_essence_of_either_term_singly,_it_

_is_no_reproach;_if_it_means_'contradicting'_such_

_essence,_Mr._Bradley_should_show_wherein_and_

_how._] But, if they contribute anything, they

_must surely be affected internally. [_Why_so,_

_if_they_contribute_only_their_surface?__In_such_

_relations_as_'on,'_'a_foot_away,'_'between,'_'next,'_

_etc.,_only_surfaces_are_in_question._] . . . If the

terms contribute anything whatever, then the

terms are affected [_inwardly_altered?_] by the

arrangement. . . . That for working purposes

we treat, and do well to treat, some relations

as external merely I do not deny, and that of

course is not the question at issue here. That

question is . . . whether in the end and in

principle a mere external relation -_i.e.,_a_relation_

_which_can_change_without_forcing_its_terms_

114

_to_change_their_nature_simultaneously_] is possible

and forced on us by the facts."(1)

Mr. Bradley next reverts to the antinomies

of space, which, according to him, prove it to

be unreal, although it appears as so prolific a

medium of external relations; and he then concludes

that "Irrationality and externality can

not be the last truth about things. Somewhere

there must be a reason why this and that appear

together. And this reason and reality

must reside in the whole from which terms and

relations are abstractions, a whole in which

their internal connection must lie, and out of

which from the background appear those fresh

results which never could have come from

the premises." And he adds that "Where the

whole is different, the terms that qualify and

contribute to it must so far be different. . . .

They are altered so far only [_How_far?_ farther_

_than_externally,_yet_not_through_and_through?_]

but still they are altered. . . . I must insist

that in each case the terms are qualified by

their whole [_Qualified_how?--Do_their_external_

115

_relations,_situations,_dates,_etc.,_changed_as_these_

_are_in_the_new_whole,_fail_to_qualify_them_'far'_

enough?_], and that in the second case there is a

whole which differs both logically and psychologically

from the first whole; and I urge that

in contributing to the change the terms so far

are altered."

Not merely the relations, then, but the terms

are altered: _Und_zwar_ 'so far.' But just _how_

far is the whole problem; and 'through-and-

through' would seem (in spite of Mr. Bradley's

somewhat undecided utterances(1)) to be the

---

1 I say 'undecided,' because, apart from the 'so far,' what sounds terribly half-hearted, there are passages in these very pages in which Mr. Bradley admits the pluralistic thesis. Read, for example, what he says, on p. 578, of a billiard ball keeping its 'character' unchanged, though, in its change of place, its 'existence' gets altered; or what he says, on p. 579, of the possibility that an abstract quality A, B, or C, in a thing, 'may throughout remain unchanged' although the thing be altered; or his admission that red-hairedness, both as analyzed out of a man and when given with the rest of him, there may be 'no change' p. 580). Why does he immediately add that for the pluralist to plead the non-mutation of such abstractions would be an _ignoratio_ _elenchi?_ It is impossible to admit it to be such. The entire _elenchus_ and inquest is just as to whether parts which you can abstract from their inner nature. If they can thus mould various wholes into new _gestalqualitaten_, then it follows that the same elements are logically able to exist in different wholes [whether physically able would depend on additional hypotheses]; that partial changes are thinkable, and through-and-through change not a dialectic necessity; that monism is only an hypothesis; and that an additively constituted universe is a rationally respectable hypothesis also. All theses of radical empiricism, in short, follow.

116

full Bradleyan answer. The 'whole' which he

here treats as primary and determinative of

each part's manner of 'contributing,' simply

_must_, when it alters, alter in its entirety. There

_must_ be total conflux of its parts, each into

and through each other. The 'must' appears

here as a _Machtspruch_, as an _ipse_dixit_ of Mr.

Bradley's absolutistically tempered 'understanding,'

for he candidly confesses that how

the parts _do_differ as they contribute to different

wholes, is unknown to him.(1)

Although I have every wish to comprehend

the authority by which Mr. Bradley's understanding

speaks, his words leave me wholly

unconverted. 'External relations' stand with

their withers all unwrung, and remain, for

aught he proves to the contrary, not only

practically workable, but also perfectly intelligible

factors of reality.

---

1 Op. cit., pp. 577-579.

117

VI

Mr. Bradley's understanding shows the

most extraordinary power of perceiving separations

and the most extraordinary impotence

in comprehending conjunctions. One would

naturally say 'neither or both,' but not so Mr.

Bradley. When a common man analyzes certain

_whats_ from out the stream of experience, he

understands their distinctness _as_thus_isolated_.

But this does not prevent him from equally

well understanding their combination with

each other _as_originally_experienced_in_the_concrete_,

or their confluence with new sensible experiences

in which they recur as 'the same.'

Returning into the stream of sensible presentation,

nouns and adjectives, and _thats_ and abstract

_whats_, grow confluent again, and the

word 'is' names all these experiences of conjunction.

Mr. Bradley understands the isolation

of the abstracts, but to understand the

combination is to him impossible.(1) "To understand

---

1 So far as I catch his state of mind, it is somewhat like this: 'Book,' 'table,' 'on' -- how does the existence of these three abstract elements result in _this_ book being livingly on _this_table. Why is n't the table on the book? Or why does n't the 'on' connect itself with another book, or something that is not a table? Must n't something _in_ each of the three elements already determine the two others to _it_, so that they do not settle elsewhere or float vaguely? Must n't the _whole_fact_be_prefigured_in_each_part_, and exist _de_jure_ before it can exist _de_fact?_ But, if so, in what can the jural existence consist, if not in a spiritual miniature of the whole fact's constitution actuating every partial factor as its purpose? But is this anything but the old metaphysical fallacy of looking behind a fact _in_esse_ for the ground of the fact, and finding it in the shape of the very same fact _in_posse?_ Somewhere we must leave off with a _constitution_ behind which there is nothing.

118

a complex AB," he says, "I must begin

with A or B. And beginning, say with A, if I

then merely find B, I have either lost A, or

I have got beside A, [_the_word_'beside'_seems_

_here_vital,_as_meaning_a_conjunction_'external'_

_and_therefore_unintelligible_] something else, and

in neither case have I understood.(1) For my

intellect can not simply unite a diversity, nor

has it in itself any form or way of togetherness,

and you gain nothing if, beside A and B,

you offer me their conjunction in fact. For to

my intellect that is no more than another external

element. And 'facts,' once for all, are

for my intellect not true unless they satisfy

it. . . . The intellect has in its nature no

principle of mere togetherness." (2)

---

1 Apply this to the case of 'book-on-table'! W.J.

2 Op. cit., pp. 570, 572.

119

Of course Mr. Bradley has a right to define

'intellect' as the power by which we perceive

separations but not unions -- provided he

give due notice to the reader. But why then

claim that such a maimed and amputated

power must reign supreme in philosophy, and

accuse on its behoof the whole empirical

world of irrationality? It is true that he elsewhere

attributes to the intellect a _proprius_

_motus_ of transition, but says that when he

looks for _these_ transitions in the detail of living

experience, he 'is unable to verify such a

solution.'(1)

Yet he never explains what the intellectual

transitions would be like in case we had them.

He only defines them negatively -- they are

not spatial, temporal, predicative, or causal;

or qualitatively or otherwise serial; or in any

way relational as we naively trace relations,

for relations _separate_ terms, and need themselves

to be hooked on _ad_infinitum_. The nearest

approach he makes to describing a truly

intellectual transition is where he speaks of

---

1 Op. cit., pp. 568, 569.

120

A and B as being 'united, each from its own

nature, in a whole which is the nature of both

alike.'(1) But this (which, _pace_ Mr. Bradley,

seems exquisitely analogous to 'taking' a congeries

in a 'lump,' if not to 'swamping') suggests

nothing but that _conflux_ which pure

experience so abundantly offers, as when

'space,' 'white' and 'sweet' are confluent in

a 'lump of sugar,' or kinesthetic, dermal, and

optical sensations confluent in 'my hand.'(2)

All that I can verify in the transitions which

Mr. Bradley's intellect desiderates as its _proprius_

_motus_ is a reminiscence of these and

other sensible conjunctions (especially space-

conjunctions), but a reminiscence so vague

that its originals are not recognized. Bradley

in short repeats the fable of the dog, the bone,

and its image in the water. With a world of

particulars, given in loveliest union, in conjunction

definitely various, and variously definite,

---

1 Op. cit., p. 570.

2 How meaningless is the contention that in such wholes (or in 'book-on-table,' 'watch-in-pocket,' etc) the relation is an additional entity _between_ the terms, needing itself to be related again to each! Both Bradley (op. cit., pp. 32-33) and Royce (_The_World_and_the_ _Individual_, vol. I, p. 128) lovingly repeat this piece of profundity.

121

the 'how' of which you 'understand' as

soon as you see the fact of them,(1) for there is

no 'how' except the constitution of the fact

as given; with all this given him, I say, in pure

experience, he asks for some ineffable union in

the abstract instead, which, if he gained it,

would only be a duplicate of what he has already

in his full possession. Surely he abuses

the privilege which society grants to all us

philosophers, of being puzzle-headed.

Polemic writing like this is odious; but with

absolutism in possession in so many quarters,

omission to defend my radical empiricism

against its best known champion would count

as either superficiality or inability. I have to

conclude that its dialectic has not invalidated

in the least degree the usual conjunctions by

which the world, as experienced, hangs so variously

together. In particular it leaves an empirical

theory of knowledge(2) intact, and lets

us continue to believe with common sense that

122

one object _may_ be known, if we have any

ground for thinking that it _is_ known, to many

knowers.

In [the next essay] I shall return to this last

supposition, which seems to me to offer other

difficulties much harder for a philosophy of

pure experience to deal with than any of

absolutism's dialectic objections.

123

IV

HOW TWO MINDS CAN KNOW

ONE THING(1)

IN [the essay] entitled 'Does Consciousness

Exist?' I have tried to show that when we call

an experience 'conscious,' that does not mean

that it is suffused throughout with a peculiar

modality of being ('psychic' being) as stained

glass may be suffused with light, but rather

that it stands in certain determinate relations

to other portions of experience extraneous to

itself. These form one peculiar 'context' for

it; while, taken in another context of experiences,

we class it as a fact in the physical

world. This 'pen,' for example, is, in the first

instance, a bald _that_, a datum, fact, phenomenon,

content, or whatever other neutral or

ambiguous name you may prefer to apply. I

called it in that article a 'pure experience.' To

get classed either as a physical pen or as some

one's percept of a pen, it must assume a _function_,

---

1 [Reprinted from _The_Journal_of_Philosophy,_Psychology_and_ _Scientific_Methods_, vol II, No. 7, March 30, 1905.]

124

and that can only happen in a more complicated

world. So far as in that world it is

a stable feature, holds ink, marks paper and

obeys the guidance of a hand, it is a physical

pen. That is what we mean by being 'physical,'

in a pen. So far as it is instable, on the

contrary, coming and going with the movements

of my eyes, altering with what I call my

fancy, continuous with subsequent experiences

of its 'having been' (in the past tense), it is the

percept of a pen in my mind. Those peculiarities

are what we mean by being 'conscious,'

in a pen.

In Section VI of another [essay](1) I tried to

show that the same _that_, the same numerically

identical pen of pure experience, can enter

simultaneously into many conscious contexts,

or, in other words, be an object for many different

minds. I admitted that I had not space

to treat of certain possible objections in that

article; but in [the last essay] I took some of

the objections up. At the end of that [essay]

I said that a still more formidable-sounding

---

1 "A World of Pure Experience," above, pp. 39-91.

125

objections remained; so, to leave my pure-

experience theory in as strong a state as possible,

I propose to consider those objections now.

I

The objections I previously tried to dispose

of were purely logical or dialectical. no one

identical term, whether physical or psychical,

it had been said, could be the subject of two

relations at once. This thesis I sought to prove

unfounded. The objections that now confront

us arise from the nature supposed to inhere in

psychic facts specifically. Whatever may be

the case with physical objects, a fact of consciousness,

it is alleged (and indeed very plausibly),

can not, without self-contradiction, be

treated as a portion of two different minds,

and for the following reasons.

In the physical world we make with impunity

the assumption that one and the same

material object can figure in an indefinitely

large number of different processes at once.

When, for instance, a sheet of rubber is pulled

at its four corners, a unit of rubber in the middle

of the sheet is affected by all four of the

126

pulls. It _transmits_ them each, as if it pulled in

four different ways at once itself. So, an air-

particle or an ether-particle 'compounds' the

different directions of movement imprinted on

it without obliterating their several individualities.

It delivers them distinct, on the contrary,

at as many several 'receivers' (ear, eye or what

not) as may be 'tuned' to that effect. The apparent

paradox of a distinctness like this surviving

in the midst of compounding is a thing

which, I fancy, the analyses made by physicists

have by this time sufficiently cleared up.

But if, on the strength of these analogies, one

should ask: "Why, if two or more lines can run

through one and the same geometrical point,

or if two or more distinct processes of activity

can run through one and the same physical

thing so that it simultaneously plays a role

in each and every process, might not two or

more streams of personal consciousness include

one and the same unit of experience so that it

would simultaneously be a part of the experience

of all the different minds?" one would be

checked by thinking of a certain peculiarity by

127

which phenomena of consciousness differ from

physical things.

While physical things, namely, are supposed

to be permanent and to have their 'states,' a

fact of consciousness exists but once and _is_ a

state. Its _esse_ is _sentiri_; it is only so far as it is felt; and it is unambiguously and unequivocally

exactly _what_ is felt The hypothesis under

consideration would, however, oblige it to be

felt equivocally, felt now as part of my mind

and again at the same time _not_ as a part of my

mind, but of yours (for my mind is _not) yours),

and this would seem impossible without doubling

it into two distinct things, or, in other

words, without reverting to the ordinary dualistic

philosophy of insulated minds each knowing

its object representatively as a third thing,

-- and that would be to give up the pure-

experience scheme altogether.

Can we see, then, any way in which a unit of

pure experience might enter into and figure in

two diverse streams of consciousness without

turning itself into the two units which, on our

hypothesis, it must not be?

128

II

There is a way; and the first step towards it

is to see more precisely how the unit enters into

either one of the streams of consciousness

alone. Just what, from being 'pure,' does its

becoming 'conscious' _once_ mean?

It means, first, that new experiences have

supervened; and, second, that they have

borne a certain assignable relation to the unit

supposed. Continue, if you please, to speak of

the pure unit as 'the pen.' So far as the pen's

successors do but repeat the pen or, being

different from it, are 'energetically'(1) related

to it, and they will form a group of stably

existing physical things. So far, however, as

its successors differ from it in another well-

determined way, the pen will figure in their

context, not as a physical, but as a mental fact.

It will become a passing 'percept,' _my_ percept

of that pen. What now is that decisive well-

determined way?

In the chapter on 'The Self,' in my _Principles_

---

1 [For an explanation of this expression, see above, p. 32.]

129

_of_Psychology_, I explained the continuous identity

of each personal consciousness as a name

for the practical fact that new experiences(1)

come which look back on the old ones, find

them 'warm,' and greet and appropriate them

as 'mine.' These operations mean, when analyzed

empirically, several tolerably definite

things, viz.:

1. That the new experience has past time for

its 'content,' and in that time a pen that 'was';

2. That 'warmth' was also about the pen,

in the sense of a group of feelings ('interest'

aroused, 'attention' turned, 'eyes' employed,

etc.) that were closely connected with it and

that now recur and evermore recur with unbroken

vividness, though from the pen of now,

which may be only an image, all such vividness

may have gone;

3. That these feelings are the nucleus of 'me';

4. That whatever once was associated with

them was, at least for that one moment,

'mine' -- my implement if associated with

---

1 I call them 'passing thoughts' in the book -- the passage in point goes from pages 330 to 342 of vol. I.

130

hand-feelings, my 'percept' only, if only eye-

feelings and attention-feelings were involved.

The pen, realized in this retrospective way

as my percept, thus figures as a fact of 'conscious'

life. But it does so only so far as 'appropriation'

has occurred; and appropriation

is _part_of_the_content_of_a_later_experience_ wholly

additional to the originally 'pure' pen. _That_

pen, virtually both objective and subjective, is

at its own moment actually and intrinsically

neither. It has to be looked back upon and

_used_, in order to be classed in either distinctive

way. But its use, so called, is in the hands of

the other experience, while _it_ stands, throughout

the operation, passive and unchanged.

If this pass muster as an intelligible account

of how an experience originally pure can enter

into one consciousness, the next question is as

to how it might conceivably enter into two.

III

Obviously no new kind of condition would

have to be supplied. All that we should have

to postulate would be a second subsequent

131

experience, collateral and contemporary with

the first subsequent one, in which a similar act

of appropriation should occur. The two acts

would interfere neither with one another nor

with the originally pure pen. It would sleep

undisturbed in its own past, no matter how

many such successors went through their several

appropriative acts. Each would know it

as 'my' percept, each would class it as a 'conscious'

fact.

Nor need their so classing it interfere in the

least with their classing it at the same time as

a physical pen. Since the classing in both cases

depends upon the taking of it in one group or

another of associates, if the superseding experience

were of wide enough 'span' it could think

the pen in both groups simultaneously, and yet

distinguish the two groups. It would then see

the whole situation conformably to what, we

call 'the representative theory of cognition,'

and that is what we all spontaneously do. As a

man philosophizing 'popularly,' I believe that

what I see myself writing with is double -- I

think it in its relations to physical nature, and

132

also in its relations to my personal life; I see

that it is in my mind, but that it also is a

physical pen.

The paradox of the same experience figuring

in two consciousnesses seems thus no paradox

at all. To be 'conscious' means not simply to

be, but to be reported, known, to have awareness

of one's being added to that being; and

this is just what happens when the appropriative

experience supervenes. The pen-experience

in its original immediacy is not aware of

itself, it simply _is_, and the second experience is

required for what we call awareness of it to

occur.(1) The difficulty of understanding what

happens here is, therefore, not a logical difficulty:

there is no contradiction involved. It is

an ontological difficulty rather. Experiences

come on an enormous scale, and if we take

---

1 Shadworth Hodgson has laid great stress on the fact that the minimum of consciousness demands two subfeelings of which the second retrospects the first. (Cf. the section 'Analysis of Minima' in his _Philosophy_of_Reflection_, vol. I, p. 248; also the chapter entitled 'The Moment of Experience' in his _Metaphysic_of_Experience_, vol. I, p. 34.) 'We live forward, but we understand backward' is a phrase of Kierkegaard's which Hoffding quotes. [H. Hoffding: "A Philosophical Confession,"

_Journal_of_Philosophy,_Psychology_and_Scientific_Methods_, vol. II, 1905, p. 86.

133

them all together, they come in a chaos of

incommensurable relations that we can not

straighten out. We have to abstract different

groups of them, and handle these separately

if we are to talk of them at all. But how the

experiences ever _get_themselves_made_, or _why_

their characters and relations are just such

as appear, we can not begin to understand..

Granting, however, that, by hook or crook,

they _can_ get themselves made, and can appear

in the successions that I have so schematically

described, then we have to confess that even

although (as I began by quoting from the adversary)

'a feeling only is as it is felt,' there is

still nothing absurd in the notion of its being

felt in two different ways at once, as yours,

namely, and as mine. It is, indeed, 'mine' only

as it is felt as mine, and 'yours' only as it is

felt as yours. But it is felt as neither _by_itself_,

but only when 'owned' by our two several remembering

experiences, just as one undivided

estate is owned by several heirs.

134

IV

One word, now, before I close, about the

corollaries of the view set forth. Since the

acquisition of conscious quality on the part of

an experience depends upon a context coming

to it, it follows that the sum total of all experiences,

having no context, can not strictly be

called conscious at all. It is a _that_, an Absolute,

a 'pure' experience on an enormous

scale, undifferentiated and undifferentiable

into thought and thing. This the post-Kantian

idealists have always practically acknowledged

by calling their doctrine an _Identitats-_

_philosophie_. The question of the _Beseelung_ of

the All of things ought not, then, even to be

asked. No more ought the question of its _truth_

to be asked, for truth is a relation inside of the

sum total, obtaining between thoughts and

something else, and thoughts, as we have seen,

can only be contextual things. In these respects

the pure experiences of our philosophy

are, in themselves considered, so many little

absolutes, the philosophy of pure experience

135

being only a more comminuted _Identitatsphilosphie_.(1)

Meanwhile, a pure experience can be postulated

with any amount whatever of span or

field. If it exert the retrospective and appropriative

function on any other piece of experience,

the latter thereby enters into its own

conscious stream. And in this operation time

intervals make no essential difference. After

sleeping, my retrospection is as perfect as it is

between two successive waking moments of my

time. Accordingly if, millions of years later, a

similarly retrospective experience should anyhow

come to birth, my present thought would

form a genuine portion of its long-span conscious

life. 'Form a portion,' I say, but not in

the sense that the two things could be entitatively

or substantively one -- they cannot,

for they are numerically discrete facts -- but

only in the sense that the _functions_ of my present

thought, its knowledge, its purpose, its

content and 'consciousness,' in short, being

inherited, would be continued practically

---

1 [Cf. below, pp. 197, 202.]

136

unchanged. Speculations like Fechner's, of an

Earth-soul, of wider spans of consciousness

enveloping narrower ones throughout the cosmos,

are, therefore, philosophically quite in

order, provided they distinguish the functional

from the entitative point of view, and do not

treat the minor consciousness under discussion

as a kind of standing material of which the

wider ones _consist_.(1)

---

1 [Cf. _A_Pluralistic_Universe_, Lect. IV, 'Concerning Fechner,' and Lect. V, 'The Compounding of Consciousness.']

137

V

THE PLACE OF AFFECTIONAL

FACTS IN A WORLD OF PURE

EXPERIENCE(1)

COMMON sense and popular philosophy are as

dualistic as it is possible to be. Thoughts, we

all naturally think, are made of one kind of

substance, and things of another. Consciousness,

flowing inside us in the forms of conception

or judgement, or concentrating itself in

the shape of passion or emotion, can be directly

felt as the spiritual activity which it is, and

known in contrast with the space-filling, objective

'content' which it envelops and accompanies.

In opposition to this dualistic

philosophy, I tried, in [the first essay] to show

that thoughts and things are absolutely homogeneous

as to their material, and that their

opposition is only one of relation and of function.

There is no thought-stuff different from

thing-stuff, I said; but the same identical piece

---

1 [Reprinted from _The_Journal_of_Philosophy,_Psychology_and_ _Scientific_Methods_, vol II,, No. 11, May 25, 1905.]

138

of 'pure experience' (which was the name I

gave to the _materia_prima_ of everything) can

stand alternately for a 'fact of consciousness'

or for a physical reality, according as it is taken

in one context or in another. For the right

understanding of what follows, I shall have to

presuppose that the reader will have read that

-essay].(1)

The commonest objection which the doctrine

there laid down runs up against is drawn

from the existence of our 'affections.' In our

pleasures and pains, our loves and fears and

angers, in the beauty, comicality, importance

or preciousness of certain objects and situations,

we have, I am told by many critics, a

great realm of experience intuitively recognized

as spiritual, made, and felt to be made,

of consciousness exclusively, and different in

nature from the space-filling kind of being

which is enjoyed by physical objects. In

Section VII, of [the first essay], I treated of

this class of experiences inadequately,

---

1 It will be still better if he shall have also read the [essay] entitled 'A World of Pure Experience,' which follows [the first] and develops its ideas still farther.

139

because I had to be brief. I now return to

the subject, because I believe that, so far from

invalidating my general thesis, these phenomena,

when properly analyzed, afford it powerful

support.

The central point of the pure-experience theory

is that 'outer' and 'inner' are names for

two groups into which we sort experiences

according to the way in which they act upon

their neighbors. Any one 'content,' such as

_hard_, let us say, can be assigned to either

group. In the outer group it is 'strong,' it acts

'energetically' and aggressively. Here whatever

is hard interferes with the space its neighbors

occupy. It dents them; is impenetrable

by them; and we call the hardness then a physical

hardness. In the mind, on the contrary,

the hard thing is nowhere in particular, it

dents nothing, it suffuses through its mental

neighbors, as it were, and interpenetrates

them. Taken in this group we call both it and

them 'ideas' or 'sensations'; and the basis of

the two groups respectively is the different

type of interrelation, the mutual impenetrability,

140

on the one hand, and the lack of physical

interference and interaction, on the other.

That what in itself is one and the same

entity should be able to function thus differently

in different contexts is a natural consequence

of the extremely complex reticulations

in which our experiences come. To her offspring

a tigress is tender, but cruel to every

other living thing -- both cruel and tender,

therefore, at once. A mass in movement resists

every force that operates contrariwise to its

own direction, but to forces that pursue the

same direction, or come in at right angles, it is

absolutely inert. It is thus both energetic and

inert; and the same is true (if you vary the

associates properly) of every other piece of

experience. It is only towards certain specific

groups of associates that the physical energies

as we call them, of a content are put forth. In

another group it may be quite inert.

It is possible to imagine a universe of experiences

in which the only alternative between

neighbors would be either physical interaction

or complete inertness. In such a world the

141

mental or the physical _status) of any piece of

experience would be unequivocal. When active,

it would figure in the physical, and when

inactive, in the mental group.

But the universe we live in is more chaotic

than this, and there is room in it for the hybrid

or ambiguous group of our affectional experiences,

of our emotions and appreciative perceptions.

In the paragraphs that follow I shall

try to show:

(1) That the popular notion that these experiences

are intuitively given as purely inner

facts is hasty and erroneous; and

(2) That their ambiguity illustrates beautifully

my central thesis that subjectivity and

objectivity are affairs not of what an experience

is aboriginally made of, but of its classification.

Classifications depend on our temporary

purposes. For certain purposes it is

convenient to take things in one set of relations,

for other purposes in another set. In the

two cases their contexts are apt to be different.

In the case of our affectional experiences we

have no permanent and steadfast purpose that

142

obliges us to be consistent, so we find it easy to

let them float ambiguously, sometimes classing

them with our feelings, sometimes with

more physical realities, according to caprice

or to the convenience of the moment. Thus

would these experiences, so far from being

an obstacle to the pure experience philosophy,

serve as an excellent corroboration of its

truth.

First of all, then, it is a mistake to say, with

the objectors whom I began by citing, that

anger, love and fear are affections purely of the

mind. That, to a great extent at any rate, they

are simultaneously affections of the body is

proved by the whole literature of the James-

Lange theory of emotion.(1) All our pains,

moreover, are local, and we are always free to

speak of them in objective as well as in subjective

terms. We can say that we are aware of

a painful place, filling a certain bigness in our

organism, or we can say that we are inwardly

in a 'state' of pain. All our adjectives of

---

1 [Cf. _The_Principles_of_Psychology_, vol. II, ch. XXV; and "The Physical Basis of Emotion," _The_Psychological_Review_, vol. I, 1894, p. 516.]

worth are similarly ambiguous -- I instanced

some of the ambiguities [in the first essay].(1)

Is the preciousness of a diamond a quality of

the gem? or is it a feeling in our mind? Practically

we treat it as both or as either, according

to the temporary direction of our thought.

'Beauty,' says Professor Santayana, 'is pleasure

objectified'; and in Sections 10 and 11 of

his work, _The_Sense_of_Beauty_, he treats in a

masterly way of this equivocal realm. The

various pleasures we receive from an object

may count as 'feelings' when we take them

singly, but when they combine in a total richness,

we call the result the 'beauty' of the

object, and treat it as an outer attribute which

our mind perceives. We discover beauty just as

we discover the physical properties of things.

Training is needed to make us expert in either

line. Single sensations also may be ambiguous.

Shall we say an 'agreeable degree of heat,' or

an 'agreeable feeling' occasioned by the degree

of heat? Either will do; and language would

lose most of its esthetic and rhetorical value

---

1 [See above, pp. 34, 35.]

144

were we forbidden to project words primarily

connoting our affections upon the objects by

which the affections are aroused. The man

is really hateful; the action really mean; the

situation really tragic -- all in themselves and

quite apart from our opinion. We even go so

far as to talk of a weary road, a giddy height, a

jocund morning or a sullen sky; and the term

'indefinite' while usually applied only to our

apprehensions, functions as a fundamental

physical qualification of things in Spencer's

'law of evolution,' and doubtless passes with

most readers for all right.

Psychologists, studying our perceptions of

movement, have unearthed experiences in

which movement is felt in general but not

ascribed correctly to the body that really

moves. Thus in optical vertigo, caused by

unconscious movements of our eyes, both we

and the external universe appear to be in a

whirl. When clouds float by the moon, it is as

if both clouds and moon and we ourselves

shared in the motion. In the extraordinary

case of amnesia of the Rev. Mr. Hanna, published

145

by Sidis and Goodhart in their important

work on _Multiple_Personality_, we read that

when the patient first recovered consciousness

and "noticed an attendant walk across the

room, he identified the movement with that of

his own. He did not yet discriminate between

his own movements and those outside himself."(1)

Such experiences point to a primitive

stage of perception in which discriminations

afterwards needful have not yet been made.

A piece of experience of a determinate sort

is there, but there at first as a 'pure' fact.

Motion originally simply _is_; only later is it

confined to this thing or to that. Something

like this is true of every experience, however

complex, at the moment of its actual presence.

Let the reader arrest himself in the act of reading

this article now. _Now_ this is a pure experience,

a phenomenon, or datum, a mere _that_ or

content of fact. _'Reading'_simply_is,_is_there_;

and whether there for some one's consciousness,

or there for physical nature, is a question

not yet put. At the moment, it is there for

---

1 Page 102.

146

neither; later we shall probably judge it to

have been there for both.

With the affectional experiences which we

are considering, the relatively 'pure' condition

lasts. In practical life no urgent need has

yet arisen for deciding whether to treat them

as rigorously mental or as rigorously physical

facts. So they remain equivocal; and, as the

world goes, their equivocality is one of their

great conveniences.

The shifting place of 'secondary qualities' in

the history of philosophy(1) is another excellent

proof of the fact that 'inner' and 'outer' are

not coefficients with which experiences come to

us aboriginally stamped, but are rather results

of a later classification performed by us for

particular needs. The common-sense stage of

thought is a perfectly definite practical halting-

place, the place where we ourselves can

proceed to act unhesitatingly. On this stage

of thought things act on each other as well

as on us by means of their secondary qualities.

---

1 [Cf. Janet and Seailles: _History_of_the_Problems_of_Philosophy_, trans. by Monahan, part I, ch. III.]

Sound, as such, goes through the air

and can be intercepted. The heat of the fire

passes over, as such, into the water which it

sets a-boiling. It is the very light of the arc-

lamp which displaces the darkness of the midnight

street, etc. By engendering and translocating

just these qualities, actively efficacious

as they seem to be, we ourselves succeed in

altering nature so as to suit us; and until more

purely intellectual, as distinguished from practical,

needs had arisen, no one ever thought

of calling these qualities subjective. When,

however, Galileo, Descartes, and others found

it best for philosophic purposes to class sound,

heat, and light along with pain and pleasure

as purely mental phenomena, they could do so

with impunity.(1)

Even the primary qualities are undergoing

the same fate. Hardness and softness are effects

on us of atomic interactions, and the

atoms themselves are neither hard nor soft,

nor solid nor liquid. Size and shape are deemed

---

1 [Cf. Descartes: _Meditation_ II; _Principles_of_Philosophy_, part I, XLVIII.]

148

subjective by Kantians; time itself is subjective

according to many philosophers;(1) and

even the activity and causal efficacy which

lingered in physics long after secondary qualities

were banished are now treated as illusory

projections outwards of phenomena of our

own consciousness. There are no activities or

effects in nature, for the most intellectual

contemporary school of physical speculation.

Nature exhibits only _changes_, which habitually

coincide with one another so that their habits

are describable in simple 'laws.'(2)

There is no original spirituality or materiality

of being, intuitively discerned, then; but

only a translocation of experiences from one

world to another; a grouping of them with

one set or another of associates for definitely

practical or intellectual ends.

I will say nothing here of the persistent

ambiguity of _relations_. They are undeniable

parts of pure experience; yet, while common

sense and what I call radical empiricism stand

---

1 [Cf. A.E. Taylor: _Elements_of_Metaphysics_, bk. III, ch. IV.] 2 [Cf. K. Pearson: _Grammar_of_Science_, ch. III.]

149

for their being objective, both rationalism and

the usual empiricism claim that they are exclusively

the 'work of the mind' -- the finite

mind or the absolute mind, as the case may be.

Turn now to those affective phenomena

which more directly concern us.

We soon learn to separate the ways in which

things appeal to our interests and emotions

from the ways in which they act upon one

another. It does not _work_ to assume that physical

objects are going to act outwardly by

their sympathetic or antipathetic qualities.

The beauty of a thing or its value is no force

that can be plotted in a polygon of compositions,

nor does its 'use' or 'significance' affect in

the minutest degree its vicissitudes or destiny

at the hands of physical nature. Chemical

'affinities' are a purely verbal metaphor; and,

as I just said, even such things as forces, tensions,

and activities can at a pinch be regarded

as anthropomorphic projections. So far, then,

as the physical world means the collection of

contents that determine in each other certain

150

regular changes, the whole collection of our

appreciative attributes has to be treated as

falling outside of it. If we mean by physical

nature whatever lies beyond the surface of our

bodies, these attributes are inert throughout

the whole extent of physical nature.

Why then do men leave them as ambiguous

as they do, and not class them decisively as

purely spiritual?

The reason would seem to be that, although

they are inert as regards the rest of physical

nature, they are not inert as regards that part

of physical nature which our own skin covers.

It is those very appreciative attributes of

things, their dangerousness, beauty, rarity,

utility, etc., that primarily appeal to our

attention. In our commerce with nature these

attributes are what give _emphasis_ to objects;

and for an object to be emphatic, whatever

spiritual fact it may mean, means also that it

produces immediate bodily effects upon us,

alterations of tone and tension, of heart-beat

and breathing, of vascular and visceral action.

The 'interesting' aspects of thins are thus

151

not wholly inert physically, though they be

active only in these small corners of physical

nature which our bodies occupy. That,

however, is enough to save them from being

classed as absolutely non-objective.

The attempt, if any one should make it, to

sort experience into two absolutely discrete

groups, with nothing but inertness in one of

them and nothing but activities in the other,

would thus receive one check. It would receive

another as soon as we examined the more

distinctively mental group; for though in that

group it be true that things do not act on one

another by their physical properties do not

dent each other or set fire to each other, they

yet act on each other in the most energetic

way by those very characters which are so

inert extracorporeally. It is by the interest

and importance that experiences have for us,

by the emotions they excite, and the purposes

they subserve, by their affective values, in

short, that their consecution in our several

conscious streams, as 'thoughts' of ours, is

mainly ruled. Desire introduces them; interest

152

holds them; fitness fixes their order and connection.

I need only refer for this aspect of

our mental life, to Wundt's article 'Ueber

psychische Causalitat,' which begins Volume

X. of his _Philosophische_Studien_.(1)

It thus appears that the ambiguous or amphibious

_status_ which we find our epithets of

value occupying is the most natural thing in

the world. It would, however, be an unnatural

status if the popular opinion which I cited

at the outset were correct. If 'physical' and

'mental' meant two different kinds of intrinsic

nature, immediately, intuitively, and

infallibly discernible, and each fixed forever

in whatever bit of experience it qualified,

one does not see how there could ever have

arisen any room for doubt or ambiguity.

But if, on the contrary, these words are

words of sorting, ambiguity is natural. For

then, as soon as the relations of a thing are

sufficiently various it can be sorted variously.

---

1 It is enough for my present purpose if the appreciative characters but _seem_ to act thus. Believers in an activity _an_sich_, other than our mental experiences of activity, will find some farther reflections on the subject in my address on 'The Experience of Activity.' [The next essay. Cf. especially, p. 169. ED.]

153

Take a mass of carrion, for example, and the

'disgustingness' which for us is a part of the

experience. The sun caresses it, and the

zephyr wooes it as if it were a bed of roses.

So the disgustingness fails to _operate_ within

the realm of suns and breezes, -- it does not

function as a physical quality. But the carrion

'turns our stomach' by what seems a direct

operation -- it _does_ function physically, therefore,

in that limited part of physics. We can

treat it as physical or as non-physical according

as we take it in the narrower or in the wider

context, and conversely, of course, we must

treat it as non-mental or as mental.

Our body itself is the palmary instance of

the ambiguous. Sometimes I treat my body

purely as a part of outer nature. Sometimes,

again, I think of it as 'mine,' I sort it with

the 'me,' and then certain local changes and

determinations in it pass for spiritual happenings.

Its breathing is my 'thinking,' its sensorial

adjustments are my 'attention,' its

kinesthetic alterations are my 'efforts,' its

visceral perturbations are my 'emotions.'

154

The obstinate controversies that have arisen

over such statements as these (which sound so

paradoxical, and which can yet be made so

seriously) prove how hard it is to decide by

bare introspection what it is in experiences

that shall make them either spiritual or

material. It surely can be nothing intrinsic in

the individual experience. It is their way of

behaving towards each other, their system of

relations, their functions; and all these things

vary with the context in which we find it

opportune to consider them.

I think I may conclude, then (and I hope

that my readers are now ready to conclude

with me), that the pretended spirituality of

our emotions and of our attributes of value,

so far from proving an objection to the philosophy

of pure experience, does, when rightly

discussed and accounted for, serve as one of

its best corroborations.

155

VI

THE EXPERIENCE OF ACTIVITY(1)

BRETHREN OF THE PSYCHOLOGICAL ASSOCIATION:

IN casting about me for a subject for your

President this year to talk about it has seemed

to me that our experiences of activity would

form a good one; not only because the topic

is so naturally interesting, and because it has

lately led to a good deal of rather inconclusive

discussion, but because I myself am growing

more and more interested in a certain systematic

way of handling questions, and want to get

others interested also, and this question strikes

me as one in which, although I am painfully

aware of my inability to communicate new

discoveries or to reach definitive conclusions,

I yet can show, in a rather definite manner,

how the method works.

---

1 President's Address before the American Psychological Association, Philadelphia Meeting, December, 1904. [Reprinted from _The_ _Psychological_Review_, vol. XII, No. 1, Jan., 1905. Also reprinted with some omissions, as Appendix B, _A_Pluralistic_Universe, pp. 370-394. Pp. 166-167 have also been reprinted in

_Some_Problems_of_Philosophy_, p. 212. The present essay is referred to in _Ibid._, p. 219, note. The author's corrections have been adopted for the present text. ED.]

156

The way of handling things I speak of, is, as

you already will have suspected, that known

sometimes as the pragmatic method, sometimes

as humanism, sometimes as Deweyism,

and in France, by some of the disciples of

Bergson, as the Philosophie nouvelle. Professor

Woodbridge's _Journal_of_Philosophy_(1) seems

unintentionally to have become a sort of meeting

place for those who follow these tendencies

in America. There is only a dim identity

among them; and the most that can be said at

present is that some sort of gestation seems to

be in the atmosphere, and that almost any day

a man with a genius for finding the right word

for things may hit upon some unifying and

conciliating formula that will make so much

vaguely similar aspiration crystallize into

more definite form.

I myself have given the name of 'radical

empiricism' to that version of the tendency in

question which I prefer; and I propose, if you

will now let me, to illustrate what I mean by

radical empiricism, by applying it to activity

---

1 [_The_Journal_of_Philosophy,_Psychology_and_Scientific_Methods_.]

157

as an example, hoping at the same time incidentally

to leave the general problem of activity

in a slightly -- I fear very slightly -- more

manageable shape than before.

Mr. Bradley calls the question of activity a

scandal to philosophy, and if one turns to the

current literature of the subject -- his own

writings included -- one easily gathers what

he means. The opponents cannot even understand

one another. Mr. Bradley says to Mr.

Ward: "I do not care what your oracle is,

and your preposterous psychology may here be

gospel if you please; . . . but if the revelation

does contain a meaning, I will commit

myself to this: either the oracle is so confused

that its signification is not discoverable, or,

upon the other hand, if it can be pinned down

to any definite statement, then that statement

will be false."(1) Mr. Ward in turn says

of Mr. Bradley: "I cannot even imagine the

state of mind to which his description applies.

. . . [It] reads like an unintentional travesty

---

1 _Appearance_and_Reality_, second edition. pp. 116-117. -- Obviously written _at_ Ward, though Ward's name is not mentioned

158

of Herbartian psychology by one who has

tried to improve upon it without being at the

pains to master it."(1) Munsterberg excludes a

view opposed to his own by saying that with

any one who holds it a _Verstandigung_ with

him is "_grundsatzlich_ausgeschlosen_"; and

Royce, in a review of _Stoud_,(2) hauls him over

the coals at great length for defending 'efficacy'

in a way which I, for one, never gathered

from reading him, and which I have

heard Stout himself say was quite foreign to

the intention of his text.

In these discussion distinct questions are

habitually jumbled and different points of

view are talked of _durcheinander_.

(1) There is a psychological question: "Have

we perceptions of activity? and if so, what are

they like, and when and where do we have

them?"

(2) There is a metaphysical question: "Is

there a _fact_ of activity? and if so, what idea

must we frame of it? What is it like? and what

---

1 [_Mind_, vol. XII, 1887, pp. 573-574.]

2 _Mind_, N.S., vol. VI, [1897], p. 379.

159

does it do, if it does anything?" And finally

there is a logical question:

(3) "Whence do we _know_ activity? By our

own feelings of it solely? or by some other

source of information?" Throughout page

after page of the literature one knows not

which of these questions is before one; and

mere description of the surface-show of experience

is proffered as if it implicitly answered

every one of them. No one of the disputants,

moreover, tries to show what pragmatic consequences

his own view would carry, or what

assignable particular differences in any one's

experience it would make if his adversary's

were triumphant.

It seems to me that if radical empiricism be

good for anything, it ought, with its pragmatic

method and its principle of pure experience,

to be able to avoid such tangles, or at least

to simplify them somewhat. The pragmatic

method starts from the postulate that there is

no difference of truth that does n't make a

difference of fact somewhere; and it seeks to

determine the meaning of all differences of

160

opinion by making the discussion hinge as soon

as possible upon some practical or particular

issue. The principle of pure experience is also

a methodological postulate. Nothing shall be admitted

as fact, it says, except what can be

experienced at some definite time by some experient;

and for every feature of fact ever so

experienced, a definite place must be found

somewhere in the final system of reality. In

other words: Everything real must be experiencable

somewhere, and every kind of thing

experienced must be somewhere real.

Armed with these rules of method let us see

what face the problems of activity present to us.

By the principle of pure experience, either

the word 'activity' must have no meaning at

all, or else the original type and model of what

it means must lie in some concrete kind of

experience that can be definitely pointed out.

Whatever ulterior judgements we may eventually

come to make regarding activity, _that_sort_

of thing will be what the judgements are about.

The first step to take, then, is to ask where in

the stream of experience we seem to find what

161

we speak of as activity. What we are to think

of the activity thus found will be a later

question.

Now it is obvious that we are tempted to

affirm activity wherever we find anything

_going_on_. Taken in the broadest sense, any

apprehension of something _doing_, is an experience

of activity. Were our world describable

only by the words 'nothing happening,'

'nothing changing,' 'nothing doing,' we should

unquestionably call it an 'inactive' world.

Bare activity then, as we may call it, means

the bare fact of event or change. 'Change taking

place' is a unique content of experience,

one of those 'conjunctive' objects which radical

empiricism seeks so earnestly to rehabilitate

and preserve. The sense of activity is thus

in the broadest and vaguest way synonymous

with the sense of 'life.' We should feel our

own subjective life at least, even in noticing

and proclaiming an otherwise inactive world.

Our own reaction on its monotony would be

the one thing experienced there in the form of

something coming to pass.

162

This seems to be what certain writers have

in mind when they insist that for an experient

to be at all is to be active. It seems to justify,

or at any rate to explain, Mr. Ward's expression

that we _are_ only as we are active,(1) for

we _are_ only as experients; and it rules out Mr.

Bradley's contention that "there is no original

experience of anything like activity."(2) What

we ought to say about activities thus elementary,

whose they are, what they effect, or

whether indeed they effect anything at all --

these are later questions, to be answered only

when the field of experience is enlarged.

Bare activity would thus be predicable,

though there were no definite direction, no

actor, and no aim. Mere restless zigzag movement,

or a wild _Ideenflucht_, or _Rhapsodie_der_

_Wharnehmungen_, as Kant would say,(2) would

---

1 _Naturalism_and_Agnosticism_, vol. II, p.245. One thinks naturally of the peripatetic _actus_primus_ and _actus_secundus_ here. ["Actus autem est _duplex_: _primus_ et _secundus_. Actus quidem primus est forma, et integritas sei. Actus autem secundus est operatio." Thomas Aquinas: _Summa_Theologica_, edition of Leo XIII, (1894), vol. I, p. 391. Cf. also Blanc: _Dictionaire_de_Philosophie_, under 'acte.' ED.]

2 [_Appearance_and_Reality_, second edition, p. 116.]

3 [_Kritik_der_reinen_Vernunft,_Werke_, (1905), vol. IV, p. 110 (trans. by Max Muller, second edition, p. 128).]

constitute and active as distinguished from an

inactive world.

But in this actual world of ours, as it is

given, a part at least of the activity comes

with definite direction; it comes with desire

and a sense of goal; it comes complicated with

resistances which it overcomes or succumbs to,

and with the efforts which the feeling of resistance

so often provokes; and it is in complex

experiences like these that the notions of

distinct agents, and of passivity as opposed

to activity arise. Here also the notion of

causal efficacy comes to birth. Perhaps the

most elaborate work ever done in descriptive

psychology has been the analysis by various

recent writers of the more complex activity-

situations.(1) In their descriptions, exquisitely

---

1 I refer to such descriptive work as Ladd's (_Psychology,_ _Descriptive_and_Explanatory_, part I, chap. V, part II, chap. XI, part III, chaps. XXV and XXVI); as Sully's (_The_Human_Mind_, part V); as Stout's (_Analytic_Psychology_, book I, chap. vi, and book II, chaps. I, II, and III); as Bradley's (in his long series of articles on Psychology in _Mind)_; as Titchener's (_Outline_of_Psychology_, part I, chap. vi); as Shand's (_Mind_, N.S., III, 449; IV, 450; VI, 289); as Ward's (_Mind_, XII, 67; 564); as Loveday's (_Mind_, N.S., X, 455); as Lipp's (Vom Fuhlen, Wollen Und Denken, 1902, chaps II, IV, VI); and as Bergson's (_Revue_Philosophique_, LIII, 1) -- to mention only a few writings which I immediately recall.

subtle some of them,91) the activity appears as

the _gestaltqualitat_ or the _fundirte_inhalt_ (or as

whatever else you may please to call the conjunctive

form) which the content falls into

when we experience it in the ways which the

describers set forth. Those factors in those

relations are what we mean by activity-situations;

and to the possible enumeration and

accumulation of their circumstances and ingredients

there would seem to be no natural

bound. Every hour of human life could contribute

to the picture gallery; and this is the

only fault that one can find with such descriptive

industry -- where is it going to stop?

Ought we to listen forever to verbal pictures

of what we have already in concrete form in

our own breasts?(2) They never take us off the

superficial plane. We knew the facts already --

less spread out and separated, to be sure -- but

---

1 Their existence forms a curious commentary on Prof. Munsterberg's dogma that will-attitudes are not describable. He himself has contributed in a superior way to their description, both in his _Willenshandlung_, and in his _Grundzuge_ [_der_Psychologie_], part II, chap. IX, section 7.

2 I ought myself to cry _peccavi_, having been a voluminous sinner in my own chapter on the will. [_Principles_of_Psychology_, vol. II, chap. XXVI.]

165

we knew them still. We always felt our own

activity, for example, as 'the expansion of an

idea with which our Self is identified, against

an obstacle';(1) and the following out of such a

definition through a multitude of cases elaborates

the obvious so as to be little more than an

exercise in synonymic speech.

All the descriptions have to trace familiar

outlines, and to use familiar terms. The activity

is, for example, attributed either to a

physical or to a mental agent, and is either

aimless or directed. If directed it shows tendency.

The tendency may or may not be resisted.

If not, we call the activity immanent, as

when a body moves in empty space by its momentum,

or our thoughts wander at their own

sweet will. If resistance is met, _its_ agent complicates

the situation. If now, in spite of resistance,

the original tendency continues, effort

makes its appearance, and along with effort,

strain or squeeze. Will, in the narrower sense

of the word, then comes upon the scene, whenever,

---

1 [Cf. F.H. Bradley, _Appearance_and_Reality_, second edition, pp. 96-97.]

166

along with the tendency, the strain and

squeeze are sustained. But the resistance may

be great enough to check the tendency, or even

to reverse its path. In that case, we (if 'we' were

the original agents or subjects of the tendency)

are overpowered. The phenomenon turns into

one of tension simply, or of necessity succumbed-

to, according as the opposing power is

only equal, or is superior to ourselves.

Whosoever describes an experience in such

terms as these describes an experience _of_ activity.

If the word have any meaning, it must

denote what there is found. _There_ is complete

activity in its original and first intention.

What is 'known-as' is what there appears.

The experiencer of such a situation possesses all

that the idea contains. He feels the tendency,

the obstacle, the will, the strain, the triumph, or

the passive giving up, just as he feels the time,

the space, the swiftness or intensity, the movement,

the weight and color, the pain and pleasure,

the complexity, or whatever remaining

characters the situation may involve. He goes

through all that ever can be imagined where

167

activity is supposed. If we suppose activities

to go on outside of our experience, it is in forms

like these that we must suppose them, or else

give them some other name; for the word

'activity' has no imaginable content whatever

save these experiences of process, obstruction,

striving, strain, or release, ultimate _qualia_ as

they are of the life given us to be known.

Were this the end of the matter, one might

think that whenever we had successfully lived

through an activity-situation we should have

to be permitted, without provoking contradiction,

to say that we had been really active,

that we had met real resistance and had really

prevailed. Lotze somewhere says that to be an

entity all that is necessary is to _gelten_ as an

entity, to operate, or be felt, experienced, recognized,

or in any way realized, as such.(1) in

our activity-experiences the activity assuredly

fulfils Lotze's demand. It makes itself

_gelten_. It is witnessed at its work. no matter

what activities there may really be in this extraordinary

universe of ours, it is impossible

---

1 [Cf. above, p. 59, note.]

168

for us to conceive of any one of them being

either lived through or authentically known

otherwise than in this dramatic shape of something

sustaining a felt purpose against felt

obstacles and overcoming or being overcome.

What 'sustaining' means here is clear to anyone

who has lived through the experience, but to

no one else; just as 'loud,' 'red,' 'sweet,' mean

something only to beings with ears, eyes, and

tongues. The _percipi_ in these originals of experience

is the _esse_; the curtain is the picture.

If there is anything hiding in the background,

it ought not to be called activity, but should

get itself another name.

This seems so obviously true that one might

well experience astonishment at finding so

many of the ablest writers on the subject

flatly denying that the activity we live through

in these situations is real. Merely to feel active

is not to be active, in their sight. The agents

that appear in the experience are not real

agents, the resistances do not really resist, the

effects that appear are not really affects at all.(1)

---

1 _Verborum_gratia_: "The feeling of activity is not able, _qua_ feeling, to tell us anything about activity" (Loveday: _Mind_, N.S., vol, X, [1901], p. 463; "A sensation or feeling or sense of activity ... is not, looked at in another way, an experience _of_ activity at all. It is a mere sensation shut up within which you could by no reflection get the idea of activity. . . . Whether this experience is or is not later on a character essential to our perception and our idea of activity, it, as it comes first, is only so for extraneous reasons and only so for an outside observer" (Bradley, _Appearance_and_Reality_, second edition, p.605); "In dem Tatigkeitsgefuhle liegt an sich nicht der geringste Beweis fur das Vorhandesein einer psychischen Tatigkeit" (Munsterberg: _Grundzuge_der_Psychologie_). I could multiply similar quotations and would have introduced some of them into my text to make it more concrete, save that the mingling of different points of view in most of these author's discussions (not in Munsterberg's) make it impossible to disentangle exactly what they mean. I am sure in any case, to be accused of misrepresenting them totally, even in this note, by omission of the context, so the less I name names and the more I stick to abstract characterization of a merely possible style of opinion, the safer it will be. And apropos of misunderstandings, I may add to this note a complaint on my own account. Professor Stoud, in the excellent chapter on 'Mental Activity,' in vol. I of his

_Analytic_Psychology_, takes me to task for identifying spiritual activity with certain muscular feelings and gives quotations to bear him out. They are from certain paragraphs on 'the Self' in which my attempt was to show what the central nucleus of the activities that we call 'ours' is. [_Principles_of_Psychology_, vol. I, pp. 299-305.] I found it in certain intracephalic movements which we habitually oppose, as 'subjective,' to the activities of the transcorporeal world. I sought to show that there is no direct evidence that we feel the activity of an inner spiritual agent as such (I should now say the activity of 'consciousness' as such, see [the first essay], 'Does Consciousness Exist?'). There are, in fact, three distinguishable 'activities' in the field of discussion: the elementary activity involved in the mere _that_ of experience, in the fact that _something_ is going on, and the farther specification of this _something_ into two _whats_, an activity felt as 'ours,' and an activity ascribed to objects. Stout, as I apprehend him, identifies 'our' activity with that of the total experience-process, and when I circumscribe it as a part thereof, accuses me of treating it as a sort of external appendage to itself (Stout: op.cit., vol. I, pp. 162-163), as if I 'separated the activity from the process which is active.' But all the processes in question are active, and their activity is inseparable from their being. My book raised only the question of _which_ activity deserved the name of 'ours.' So far as we are 'persons,' and contrasted and opposed to an 'environment,' movements in our body figure as our activities; and I am unable to find any other activities that are ours in this strictly personal sense. There is a wider sense in which the whole 'choir of heaven and furniture of the earth,' and their activities, are ours, for they are our 'objects.' But 'we' are here only another name for the total process of experience, another name for all that is, in fact; and I was dealing with the personal and individualized self exclusively in the passages with which Professor Stout finds fault.

The individualized self, which I believe to be the only thing properly called self, is a part of the content of the world experienced. The world experienced (otherwise called the 'field of consciousness') comes at all times with our body at its centre, centre of vision, centre of action, centre of interest. Where the body is is 'here': when the body acts is 'now'; what the body touches is 'this'; all other things are 'there' and 'then' and 'that.' These words of emphasized position imply a systematization of things with reference to a focus of action and interest which lies in the body; and the systematization is now so instinctive (was it ever not so?) that no developed or active experience exists for us at all except in that ordered form. So far as 'thoughts' and 'feelings' can be active, there activity terminates in the activity of the body, and only through first arousing its activities can they begin to change those of the rest of the world. [Cf. also

_A_Pluralistic_Universe_, p. 344, note 8. ED.] The body is the storm centre, the origin of co-ordinates, the constant place of stress in all that experience-train. Everything circles round it, and is felt from its point of view. The word 'I,' then, is primarily a noun of position, just like 'this' and 'here.' Activities attached to 'this' position have prerogative emphasis, and, if activities have feelings, must be felt in a particular way. The word 'my designates the kind of emphasis. I see no inconsistency whatever in defending, on the one hand, 'my' activities as unique and opposed to those of outer nature, and, on the other hand, in affirming, after introspection, that they consist in movements in the head. The 'my' of them is the emphasis, the feeling of perspective-interest in which they are dyed.

169

It is evident from this that mere descriptive

analysis of any one of our activity-experiences

is not the whole story, that there is something

170

still to tell _about_ them that has led such able

writers to conceive of a _Simon-pure_ activity,

an activity _an_sich_, that does, and does n't

171

merely appear to us to do, and compared with

whose real doing all this phenomenal activity

is but a specious sham.

The metaphysical question opens here; and

I think that the state of mind of one possessed

by it is often something like this: "It is all very

well," we may imagine him saying, "to talk

about certain experience-series taking on the

form of feelings of activity, just as they might

take on musical or geometric forms. Suppose

that they do so; suppose we feel a will to stand

a strain. Does our feeling do more than _record_

the fact that the strain is sustained? The _real_

activity, meanwhile, is the _doing_ of the fact;

and what is the doing made of before the record

is made. What in the will _enables_ it to act thus?

And these trains of experience themselves, in

which activities appear, what makes them _go_

at all? Does the activity in one bit of experience

bring the next bit into being? As an empiricist

172

you cannot say so, for you have just

declared activity to be only a kind of synthetic

object, or conjunctive relation experienced between

bits of experience already made. But

what made them at all? What propels experience

_uberhaupt_ into being? _There_ is the activity

that _operates_; the activity _felt_ is only

its superficial sign."

To the metaphysical question, popped upon

us in this way, I must pay serious attention

ere I end my remarks; but, before doing so, let

me show that without leaving the immediate

reticulations of experience, or asking what

makes activity itself act, we still find the distinction

between less real and more real activities

forced upon us, and are driven to much

soul-searching on the purely phenomenal plane.

We must not forget, namely, in talking of

the ultimate character of our activity-experiences,

that each of them is but a portion of a

wider world, one link in the vast chain of processes

of experience out of which history is

made. Each partial process, to him who lives

through it, defines itself by its origin and its

173

goal; but to an observer with a wider mind-

span who should live outside of it, that goal

would appear but as a provisional halting-

place, and the subjectively felt activity would

be seen to continue into objective activities

that led far beyond. We thus acquire a habit,

in discussing activity-experiences, of defining

them by their relation to something more. If

an experience be one of narrow span, it will be

mistaken as to what activity it is and whose.

You think that _you_ are acting while you are

only obeying someone's push. You think you

are doing _this_, but you are doing something of

which you do not dream. For instance, you

think you are but drinking this glass; but you

are really creating the liver-cirrhosis that will

end your days. You think you are just driving

this bargain, but, as Stevenson says somewhere,

you are laying down a link in the policy

of mankind.

Generally speaking, the onlooker, with his

wider field of vision, regards the _ultimate_outcome_

of an activity as what it is more really

doing; and _the_most_previous_agent_ ascertainable,

174

being the first source of action, he regards

as the most real agent in the field. The others

but transmit the agent's impulse; on him

we put responsibility; we name him when one

asks us 'Who's to blame?'

But the most previous agents ascertainable,

instead of being a longer span, are often of

much shorter span than the activity in view.

Brain-cells are our best example. My brain-

cells are believed to excite each other from

next to next (by contiguous transmission of

katabolic alteration, let us say) and to have

been doing so long before this present stretch

of lecturing-activity on my part began. If any

one cell-group stops its activity, the lecturing

will cease or show disorder of form. _Cessante_

_causa,_cessat_et_effectus_ -- does not this look as

if the short-span brain activiteis were the more

real activities, and the lecturing activities

on my part only their effects? Moreover, as

Hume so clearly pointed out,(1) in my mental

activity-situation the words physically to be

---

1 [_Enquiry_Concerning_Human_Understanding_, sect VII, part I, Selby-Bigge's edition, pp. 65 ff.]

175

uttered are represented as the activity's immediate

goal. These words, however, cannot

be uttered without intermediate physical processes

in the bulb and vagi nerves, which processes

nevertheless fail to figure in the mental

activity-series at all. That series, therefore,

since it leaves out vitally real steps of action,

cannot represent the real activities. It is something

purely subjective; the _facts_ of activity

are elsewhere. They are something far more

interstitial, so to speak, than what my feelings

record.

The _real_ facts of activity that have in point

of fact been systematically pleaded for by

philosophers have, so far as my information

goes, been of three principal types.

The first type takes a consciousness of wider

time-span than ours to be the vehicle of the

more real activity. Its will is the agent, and its

purpose is the action done.

The second type assumes that 'ideas' struggling

with one another are the agents, and

that the prevalence of one set of them is the

action.

176

The third type believes that never-cells are

the agents, and that resultant motor discharges

are the acts achieved.

Now if we must de-realize our immediately

felt activity-situations for the benefit of either

of these types of substitute, we ought to know

what the substitution practically involves.

_What_practical_difference_ought_it_to_make_if_,

instead of saying naively that 'I' am active

now in delivering this address, I say that _a_

_wider_thinker_is_active_, or that _certain_ideas_are_

_active_, or that _certain_nerve-cells_are_active_, in

producing the result?

This would be the pragmatic meaning of the

three hypotheses. Let us take them in succession

in seeking a reply.

If we assume a wider thinker, it is evident

that his purposes envelope mine. I am really

lecturing _for_ him; and although I cannot surely

know to what end, yet if I take him religiously,

I can trust it to be a good end, and willingly

connive. I can be happy in thinking that my

activity transmits his impulse, and that his

ends prolong my own. Son long as I take him

177

religiously, in short, he does not de-realize my

activities. He tends rather to corroborate the

reality of them, so long as I believe both them

and him to be good.

When now we turn to ideas, the case is different,

inasmuch as ideas are supposed by the

association psychology to influence each other

only from next to next. The 'span' of an idea

or pair of ideas, is assumed to be much smaller

instead of being larger than that of my total

conscious field. The same results may get

worked out in both cases, for this address is

being given anyhow. But the ideas supposed

to 'really' work it out had no prevision of the

whole of it; and if I was lecturing for an absolute

thinker in the former case, so, by similar

reasoning, are my ideas now lecturing for me,

that is, accomplishing unwittingly a result

which I approve and adopt. But, when this

passing lecture is over, there is nothing in the

bare notion that ideas have been its agents

that would seem to guarantee that my present

purposes in lecturing will be prolonged. _I_ may

have ulterior developments in view; but there

178

is no certainty that my ideas as such will wish

to, or be able to, work them out.

The like is true if nerve-cells be the agents.

The activity of a nerve-cell must be conceived

of as a tendency of exceedingly short reach, an

'impulse' barely spanning the way to the next

cell -- for surely that amount of actual 'process'

must be 'experienced' by the cells if what

happens between them is to deserve the name

of activity at all. But here again the gross

resultant, as _I_ perceive it, is indifferent to the

agents, and neither wished or willed or foreseen.

Their being agents now congruous with

my will gives me no guarantee that like results

will recur again from their activity. In point

of fact, all sorts of other results do occur. My

mistakes, impotencies, perversions, mental obstructions,

and frustrations generally, are also

results of the activity of cells. Although these

are letting me lecture now, on other occasions

they make me do things that I would willingly

not do.

The question _Whose_is_the_real_activity?_ is

thus tantamount to the question _What_will_be_

179

_the_actual_results?_ Its interest is dramatic; how

will things work out? If the agents are of

one sort, one way; if of another sort, they may

work out differently. The pragmatic

meaning of the various alternatives, in short,

is great. It makes no merely verbal difference

which opinion we take up.

You see it is the old dispute come back!

Materialism and teleology; elementary short-

span actions summing themselves 'blindly,' or

far foreseen ideals coming with effort into act.

Naively we believe, and humanly and dramatically

we like to believe, that activities

both of wider and of narrower span are at

work in life together, that both are real, and

that the long-span tendencies yoke the others

in their service, encouraging them in the right

direction, and damping them when they tend

in other ways. But how to represent clearly

the _modus_operandi_ of such steering of small

tendencies by large ones is a problem which

metaphysical thinkers will have to ruminate

upon for many years to come. Even if such

control should eventually grow clearly picturable,

180

the question how far it is successfully

exerted in this actual world can be answered

only by investigating the details of fact. No

philosophic knowledge of the general nature

and constitution of tendencies, or of the relation

of larger to smaller ones, can help us to

predict which of all the various competing

tendencies that interest us in this universe are

likeliest to prevail. We know as an empirical

fact that far-seeing tendencies often carry out

their purpose, but we know also that they are

often defeated by the failure of some contemptibly

small process on which success depends.

A little thrombus in a statesman's

meningeal artery will throw an empire out of

gear. I can therefore not even hint at any solution

of the pragmatic issue. I have only wished

to show you that that issue is what gives the

real interest to all inquiries into what kinds of

activity may be real. Are the forces that really

act in the world more foreseeing or more blind?

As between 'our' activities as 'we' experience

them, and those of our ideas, or of our brain-

cells, the issue is well-defined.

181

I said a while back(1) that I should return to

the 'metaphysical' question before ending; so,

with a few words about that, I will now close

my remarks.

In whatever form we hear this question propounded,

I think that it always arises from two

things, a belief that _causality_ must be exerted

in activity, and a wonder as to how causality is

made. If we take an activity-situation at its

face-value, it seems as if we caught _in_flagrante_

_delicto_ the very power that makes facts come

and be. I now am eagerly striving, for example,

to get this truth which I seem half to

perceive, into words which shall make it show

more clearly. If the words come, it will seem as

if the striving itself had drawn or pulled them

into actuality out from the state of merely

possible being in which they were. How is this

feat performed? How does the pulling _pull?_

How do I get my hold on words not yet existent,

and when they come by what means have

I _made_ them come? Really it is the problem of

creation; for in the end the question is: How do

---

1 Page 172.

182

I make them _be?_ Real activities are those

that really make things be, without which

the things are not, and with which they are

there. Activity, so far as we merely feel it, on

the other hand, is only an impression of ours,

it may be maintained; and an impression is,

for all this way of thinking, only a shadow of

another fact.

Arrived at this point, I can do little more

than indicate the principles on which, as it

seems to me, a radically empirical philosophy

is obliged to rely in handling such a dispute.

If there _be_ real creative activiteis in being,

radical empiricism must say, somewhere they

must be immediately lived. Somewhere the

_that_ of efficacious causing and the _what_ of it

must be experienced in one, just as the what

and the that of 'cold' are experienced in one

whenever a man has the sensation of cold here

and now. It boots not to say that our sensations

are fallible. They are indeed; but to see

the thermometer contradict us when we say 'it

is cold' does not abolish cold as a specific nature

from the universe. Cold is the arctic

183

circle if not here. Even so, to feel that our

train is moving when the train beside our window

moves, to see the moon through a telescope

come twice as near, or to see two pictures

as one solid when we look through a

stereoscope at them, leaves motion, nearness,

and solidity still in being -- if not here,

yet each in its proper seat elsewhere. And

wherever the seat of real causality _is_, as ultimately

known 'for true' (in nerve-processes,

if you will, that cause our feelings of activity

as well as the movements which these

seem to prompt), a philosophy of pure experience

can consider the real causation as no other

_nature_ of thing than that which even our

most erroneous experiences appears to be at

work. Exactly what appears there is what we

_mean_ by working, though we may later come

to learn that working was not exactly _there_.

Sustaining, persevering, striving, paying with

effort as we go, hanging on, and finally achieving

our intention -- this _is_ action, this _is_ effectuation

in the only shape in which, by a pure

experience-philosophy, the whereabouts of it

184

anywhere can be discussed. Here is creation

in its first intention, here is causality at work.(1)

To treat this offhand as the bare illusory surface

of a world whose real causality is an unimaginable

ontological principle hidden in the

cubic deeps, is, for the more empirical way of

thinking, only animism in another shape. You

explain your given fact by your 'principle,' but

the principle itself, when you look clearly at it,

turns out to be nothing but a previous little

spiritual copy of the fact. Away from that one

and only kind of fact your mind, considering

causality, can never get.(2)

---

1 Let me not be told that this contradicts [the first essay], 'Does Consciousness Exist?' (see especially page 32), in which it was said that while 'thoughts' and 'things' have the same natures, the natures work 'energetically' on each other in the things (fire burns, water wets, etc.) but not in the thoughts. Mental activity- trains are composed of thoughts, yet their members do work on each other, they check, sustain, and introduce. They do so when the activity is merely associational as well as when effort is there. But, and this is my reply, they do so by other parts of their nature than those that energize physically. One thought in every developed activity-series is a desire or thought of purpose, and all the other thoughts acquire a feeling tone from their relation of harmony or oppugnancy to this. The interplay of these secondary tones (among which 'interest,' 'difficulty,' and 'effort' figure) runs the drama in the mental series. In what we term the physical drama these qualities play absolutely no part. The subject needs careful working out; but I can see no inconsistency.

2 I have found myself more than once accused in print of being the assertor of a metaphysical principle of activity. Since literary misunderstandings retard the settlement of problems, I should like to say that such an interpretation of the pages I have published on Effort and on Will is absolutely foreign to what I mean to express. [_Principles_of_Psychology_, vol II, ch. XXVI.] I ow all my doctrines on this subject to Renouvier; and Renouvier, as I understand him, is (or at any rate then was) an out and out phenomenalist, a denier of 'forces' in the most strenuous sense. [Cf. Ch. Renouvier:

_Esquisse_d'une_Classification_Systematique_des_Doctrines_Philoso phiques_ (1885), vol. II, pp. 390-392; _Essais_de_Critique_Generale_ (1859), vol. II, sections ix, xiii. For an acknowledgement of the author's general indebtedness to Renouvier, cf. _Some_Problems_of_Philosophy_, p. 165, note. ED.] Single clauses in my writing, or sentences read out of their connection, may possibly have been compatible with a

transphenomenal principle of energy; but I defy anyone to show a single sentence which, taken with its context, should be naturally held to advocate that view. The misinterpretation probably arose at first from my defending (after Renouvier) the indeterminism of our efforts. 'Free will' was supposed by my critics to involve a supernatural agent. As a matter of plain history the only 'free will' I have ever thought of defending is the character of novelty in fresh activity-situations. If an activity-process is the form of a whole 'field of consciousness,' and if each field of consciousness is not only in its totality unique (as is now commonly admitted) but has its elements unique (since in that situation they are all dyed in the total) then novelty is perpetually entering the world and what happens there is not pure _repetition_, as the dogma of the literal uniformity of nature requires.

Activity-situations come, in short, each with an original touch. A 'principle' of free will if there were one, would doubtless manifest itself in such phenomena, but I never say, nor do I now see, what the principle could do except rehearse the phenomenon beforehand, or why it ever should be invoked.

186

for philosophy is to leave off grubbing underground

for what effects effectuation, or what

makes action act, and to try to solve the concrete

questions of where effectuation in this

world is located, of which things are the true

causal agents there, and of what the more

remote effects consist.

From this point of view the greater sublimity

traditionally attributed to the metaphysical

inquiry, the grubbing inquiry, entirely disappears.

If we could know what causation

really and transcendentally is in itself, the only

_use_ of the knowledge would be to help us to

recognize an actual cause when we had one,

and so to track the future course of operations

more intelligently out. The mere abstract

inquiry into causation's hidden nature

is not more sublime than any other inquiry

equally abstract. Causation inhabits no more

sublime level than anything else. It lives,

apparently, in the dirt of the world as well

as in the absolute, or in man's unconquerable

mind. The worth and interest of the world

consists not in its elements, be these elements

187

things, or be they the conjunctions of things;

it exists rather in the dramatic outcome in

the whole process, and in the meaning of the

succession stages which the elements work out.

My colleague and master, Josiah Royce, in

a page of his review of Stout's _Analytic_Psychology(1)

has some fine words on this point

with which I cordially agree. I cannot agree

with his separating the notion of efficacy from

that of activity altogether (this I understand

to be one contention of his) for activities are

efficacious whenever they are real activities at

all. But the inner nature both of efficacy and

of activity are superficial problems, I understand

Royce to say; and the only point for us

in solving them would be their possible use in

helping us to solve the far deeper problem of

the course and meaning of the world of life.

Life, says our colleague, is full of significance,

of meaning, of success and of defeat, of hoping

and of striving, of longing, of desire, and of

inner value. It is a total presence that embodies

worth. To live our own lives better in

---

1 _Mind_, N.S., vol. VI, 1897; cf. pp. 392-393.

188

this presence is the true reason why we wish to

know the elements of things; so even we psychologists

must end on this pragmatic note.

The urgent problems of activity are thus

more concrete. They are all problems of the

true relation of longer-span to shorter-span

activities. When, for example, a number of

'ideas' (to use the name traditional in psychology)

grow confluent in a larger field of

consciousness, do the smaller activities still

co-exist with the wider activities then experienced

by the conscious subject? And, if so,

do the wide activities accompany the narrow

ones inertly, or do they exert control? Or do

they perhaps utterly supplant and replace

them and short-circuit their effects? Again,

when a mental activity-process and a brain-

cell series of activities both terminate in the

same muscular movement, does the mental

process steer the neural processes or not? Or,

on the other hand, does it independently short-

circuit their effects? Such are the questions

that we must begin with. But so far am I from

suggesting any definitive answer to such questions,

189

that I hardly yet can put them clearly.

They lead, however, into that region of pan-

psychic and ontologic speculation of which

Professors Bergson and Strong have lately enlarged

the literature in so able and interesting

a way.(1) The result of these authors seem

in many respects dissimilar, and I understand

them as yet but imperfectly; but I cannot help

suspecting that the direction of their work is

very promising, and that they have the hunter's

instinct for the fruitful trails.

---

1 [Cf. _A_Pluralistic_Universe_, Lect. VI (on Bergson); H. Bergson: _Creative_Evolution_, trans. by A. Mitchell; C.A. Strong:

_Why_the_Mind_Has_a_Body_, ch. XII. ED.]

190

VII

THE ESSENCE OF HUMANISM(1)

HUMANISM is a ferment that has 'come to

stay.'(2) It is not a single hypothesis of theorem,

and it dwells on no new facts. It is

rather a slow shifting in the philosophic perspective,

making things appear as from a new

centre of interest or point of sight. Some

writers are strongly conscious of the shifting,

others half unconscious, even though their own

vision may have undergone much change. The

result is no small confusion in debate, the half-conscious

humanists often taking part against

the radical ones, as if they wished to count

upon the other side.(3)

---

1 [Reprinted from

_The_Journal_of_Philosophy,_Psychology_and_Scientific_Methods_, vol. II, No. 5, March 2, 1905. Also reprinted, with slight changes in _The_Meaning_of_Truth_, pp. 121-135. The author's corrections have been adopted for the present text. ED.]

2 [Written _apropos_ of the appearance of three articles in _Mind_, N.S., vol. XIV, No. 53, January, 1905: "'Absolute' and 'Relative' Truth," H.H.Joachim; "Professor James on 'Humanism and Truth,'" H.W.B.Joseph; "Applied Axioms," A. Sidgwick. Of these articles the second and third "continue the humanistic (or pragmatistic) controversy," the first "deeply connects with it." ED.]

3 Professor Baldwin, for example. His address 'On Selective Thinking' (_Psychological_Review_, [vol. V], 1898, reprinted in his volume, _Development_and_Evolution) seems to me an unusually well- written pragmatic manifesto. Nevertheless in 'The Limits of Pragmatism' (ibid., [vol. XI], 1904), he (much less clearly) joins in the attack.

191

If humanism really be the name for such

a shifting of perspective, it is obvious that

the whole scene of the philosophic stage will

change in some degree if humanism prevails.

The emphasis of things, their foreground and

background distribution, their sizes and values,

will not keep just the same.(1) If such

pervasive consequences be involved in humanism,

it is clear that no pains which philosophers

may take, first in defining it, and then in

furthering, checking, or steering its progress,

will be thrown away.

It suffers badly at present from incomplete

definition. Its most systematic advocates,

Schiller and Dewey, have published fragmentary

---

1 The ethical changes, it seems to me, are beautifully made evident in Professor Dewey's series of articles, which will never get the attention they deserve till they are printed in a book. I mean: 'The Significance of Emotions,' _Psychological_Review_, vol. II, [1895], p. 13; 'The Reflex Arc Concept in Psychology,' ibid., vol. III [1896], p. 357; 'Psychology and Social Practice,' ibid., vol. VII, [1900], p. 105; 'Interpretation of Savage Mind,' ibid., vol. IX, [1902], p.217; 'Green's Theory of the Moral Motive,' _Philosophical_Review_, vol. I, [1892], p. 593; 'Self-realization as the Moral Ideal,' ibid., vol. II, [1893], p. 652; 'The Psychology of Effort,' ibid., vol. VI, [1897], p.43; 'The Evolutionary Method as Applied to Morality,' ibid., vol XI, [1902], pp. 107, 353; 'Evolution and Ethics,' _Monist_, vol. VIII, [1898], p.321; to mention only a few.

192

programs only; and its bearing on many

vital philosophic problems has not been traced

except by adversaries who, scenting heresies in

advance, have showered blows on doctrines --

subjectivism and scepticism, for example --

that no good humanist finds it necessary to

entertain. By their still greater reticences, the

anti-humanists have, in turn, perplexed the

humanists. Much of the controversy has involved

the word 'truth.' It is always good in

debate to know your adversary's point of view

authentically. But the critics of humanism

never define exactly what the word 'truth'

signifies when they use it themselves. The

humanists have to guess at their view; and

the result has doubtless been much at beating of

the air. Add to all this, great individual differences

in both camps, and it becomes clear that

nothing is so urgently needed, at the stage

which things have reached at present, as a

sharper definition by each side of its central

point of view.

Whoever will contribute any touch of

sharpness will help us to make sure of what's

193

what and who is who. Anyone can contribute

such a definition, and, without it, no one

knows exactly where he stands. If I offer my

own provisional definition of humanism(1) now

and here, others may improve it, some adversary

may be led to define his own creed more sharply

by the contrast, and a certain quickening

of the crystallization of general opinion

may result.

I

The essential service of humanism, as I conceive

the situation, is to have seen that _though_

_one_part_of_our_experience_may_lean_upon_another_

_part_to_make_it_what_it_is_in_any_one_of_several_

_aspects_in_which_it_may_be_considered,_experience_

_as_a_whole_is_self-containing_and_leans_

_on_nothing_.

Since this formula also expresses the main

contention of transcendental idealism, it needs

abundant explication to make it unambiguous.

---

1 [The author employs the term 'humanism' either as a synonym for 'radical empiricism' (cf. e.g, above, p. 156); or as that general philosophy of life of which 'radical empiricism' is the theoretical ground (cf. below, p. 194). For other discussions of 'humanism,' cf. below, essay XI, and _The_Meaning_of)Truth_, essay III. ED.]

194

It seems, at first sight, to confine itself to

denying theism and pantheism. But, in fact,

it need not deny either; everything would

depend on the exegesis; and if the formula

ever became canonical, it would certainly

develop both right-wing and left-wing interpreters.

I myself read humanism theistically

and pluralistically. If there be a God, he is

no absolute all-experiencer, but simply the

experiencer of widest actual conscious span.

Read thus, humanism is for me a religion

susceptible of reasoned defence, though I am

well aware how many minds there are to whom

it can appeal religiously only when it has

been monistically translated. Ethically the

pluralistic form of it takes for me a stronger

hold on reality than any other philosophy I

know of -- it being essentially a _social_ philosophy,

a philosophy of _'co,'_ in which conjunctions

do the work. But my primary reason

for advocating it is its matchless intellectual

economy. It gets rid, not only of the standing

'problems' that monism engenders ('problem

of evil,' 'problem of freedom,' and the

like), but of other metaphysical mysteries and

paradoxes as well.

It gets rid, for example, of the whole agnostic

controversy, by refusing to entertain the hypothesis

of trans-empirical reality at all. It gets rid

of any need for an absolute of the Bradleyan

type (avowedly sterile for intellectual

purposes) by insisting that the conjunctive

relations found within experience are faultlessly

real. It gets rid of the need of an absolute

of the Roycean type (similarly sterile) by

its pragmatic treatment of the problem of

knowledge [a treatment of which I have already

given a version in two very inadequate

articles].(1) As the views of knowledge, reality

and truth imputed to humanism have been

those so far most fiercely attacked, it is in

regard to these ideas that a sharpening of

focus seems most urgently required. I proceed

therefore to bring the view which _I_ impute

to humanism in these respects into focus as

briefly as I can.

---

1 [Omitted from reprint in _Meaning_of_Truth_. The articles referred to are 'Does Consciousness Exist?' and 'A World of Pure Experience,' reprinted above.]

196

II

If the central humanistic thesis, printed

above in italics, be accepted, it will follow

that, if there be any such thing at all as knowing,

the knower and the object known must

both be portions of experience. One part of

experience must, therefore, either

(1) Know another part of experience -- in

other words, parts must, as Professor Woodbridge

says,(1) represent _one_another_ instead of

representing realities outside of 'consciousness'

-- this case is that of conceptual knowledge; or else

(2) They must simply exist as so many ultimate

_thats_ or facts of being, in the first instance;

an then, as a secondary complication,

and without doubling up its entitative singleness,

any one and the same _that_ must figure

alternately as a thing known and as a knowledge

of the thing, by reason of two divergent

kinds of context into which, in the general

course of experience, it gets woven.(2)

---

1 In _Science_, November 4, 1904, p. 599.

2 This statement is probably excessively obscure to any who has not read my two articles, 'Does Consciousness Exist?' and 'A World of Pure Experience.'

197

This second case is that of sense-perception.

There is a stage of thought that goes beyond

common sense, and of it I shall say more presently;

but the common-sense stage is a perfectly

definite halting-place of thought, primarily

for the purposes of action; and, so long

as we remain on the common-sense stage of

thought, object and subject _fuse_ in the fact of

'presentation' or sense-perception -- the pen

and hand which I now _see_ writing, for example,

_are_ the physical realities which those words

designate. In this case there is no self-transcendency

implied in the knowing. Humanism,

here, is only a more comminuted _Identitasphilosophie_.(1)

In case (1), on the contrary, the representative

experience does transcend itself in knowing

the other experience that is its object. No

one can talk of the knowledge of the one by the

other without seeing them as numerically distinct

entities, of which the one lies beyond the

other and away from it, along some direction

---

1 [Cf. above, p. 134; and below, p.202.]

198

and with some interval, that can be definitely

named. But, if the talker be a humanist, he

must also see this distance-interval concretely

and pragmatically, and confess it to consist

of other intervening experiences -- of possible

ones, at all events, if not of actual. To call my

present idea of my dog, for example, cognitive

of the real dog means that, as the actual tissue

of experience is constituted, the idea is capable

of leading into a chain of other experiences

on my part that go from next to next and

terminate at last in vivid sense-perceptions

of a jumping, barking, hairy body. Those _are_

the real dog, the dog's full presence, for my

common sense. If the supposed talker is a

profound philosopher, although they may not

_be_ the real dog for him, they _mean_ the real dog,

are practical substitutes for the real dog, as

the representation was a practical substitute

for them, that real dog being a lot of atoms,

say, or of mind-stuff, that lie _where_ the sense-

perceptions lie in his experience as well as in

my own.

199

III

The philosopher here stands for the stage of

thought that goes beyond the stage of common

sense; and the difference is simply that he

'interpolates' and 'extrapolates,' where common

sense does not. For common sense, two

men see the same identical real dog. Philosophy,

noting actual differences in their perceptions,

points out the duality of these latter,

and interpolates something between them as

a more real terminus -- first, organs, viscera,

etc.; next, cells; then, ultimate atoms; lastly,

mind-stuff perhaps. The original sense-termini

of the two men, instead of coalescing with

each other and with the real dog-object, as at

first supposed, are thus help by philosophers to

be separated by invisible realities with which

at most, they are conterminous.

Abolish, now, one of the percipients, and

the interpolation changes into 'extrapolation.'

The sense-terminus of the remaining percipient

is regarded by the philosopher as not quite

reaching reality. He has only carried the procession

of experiences, the philosopher thinks,

200

to a definite, because practical, halting-place

somewhere on the way towards an absolute

truth that lies beyond.

The humanist sees all the time, however,

that there is no absolute transcendency even

about the more absolute realities thus conjectured

or believed in. The viscera and cells

are only possible percepts following upon that

of the outer body. The atoms again, though

we may never attain to human means of perceiving

them, are still defined perceptually.

The mind-stuff itself is conceived as a kind

of experience; and it is possible to frame the

hypothesis (such hypotheses can by no logic

be excluded from philosophy) of two knowers

of a piece of mind-stuff and the mind-stuff

itself becoming 'confluent' at the moment at

which our imperfect knowing might pass into

knowing of a completed type. Even so do you

and I habitually represent our two perceptions

and the real dog as confluent, though only provisionally,

and for the common-sense stage

of thought. If my pen be inwardly made of

mind-stuff, there is no confluence _now_ between

201

that mind-stuff and my visual perception of

the pen. But conceivably there might come to

be such confluence; for, in the case of my hand,

the visual sensations and the inward feelings

of the hand, its mind-stuff, so to speak, are even

now as confluent as any two things can be.

There is, thus, no breach in humanistic

epistemology. Whether knowledge be taken

as ideally perfected, or only as true enough to

pass muster for practice, it is hung on one continuous

scheme. Reality, howsoever remote, is

always defined as a terminus within the general

possibilities of experience; and what knows it is

defined as an experience _that_'represents'_it,_in_

_the_sense_of_being_substitutable_for_it_in_our_thinking_

because it leads to the same associates, _or_

_in_the_sense_of_'point_to_it'_ through a chain

of other experiences that either intervene or

may intervene.

Absolute reality here bears the same relation

to sensation as sensation bears to conception

or imagination. Both are provisional or final

termini, sensation being only the terminus

at which the practical man habitually stops,

202

while the philosopher projects a 'beyond' in

the shape of more absolute reality. These

termini, for the practical and the philosophical

stages of thought respectively, are self-

supporting. They are not 'true' of anything

lese, they simply _are_, are _real_. They 'lean

on nothing,' as my italicized formula said.

Rather does the whole fabric of experience

lean on them, just as the whole fabric of the

solar system, including many relative positions,

leans, for its absolute position in space,

on any one of its constituent stars. Here,

again, one gets a new _Identitatsphilosophie_ in

pluralistic form.(1)

IV

If I have succeeded in making this at all

clear (though I fear that brevity and abstractness

between them may have made me fail),

the reader will see that the 'truth' of our mental

operations must always ben an intra-experiential

affair. A conception is reckoned true by

common sense when it can be made to lead to a

---

1 [Cf. above, pp. 134, 197.]

203

sensation. The sensation, which for common

sense is not so much 'true' as 'real,' is held to

be _provisionally_ true by the philosopher just

in so far as it _covers_ (abuts at, or occupies the

place of) a still more absolutely real experience,

in the possibility of which to come remoter

experient the philosopher finds reason

to believe.

Meanwhile what actually _does_ count for true

to any individual trower, whether he be philosopher

or common man, is always a result of his

_apperceptions_. If a novel experience, conceptual

or sensible, contradict too emphatically our

pre-existent system of beliefs, in ninety-nine

cases out of a hundred it is treated as false.

Only when the older and the newer experiences

are congruous enough to mutually apperceive

and modify each other, does what we treat as

an advance in truth result. [Having written of

this point in an article in reply to Mr. Joseph's

criticism of my humanism, I will say no more

about truth here, but refer the reader to that

review.(1)] In no case, however, need truth

---

1 [Omitted from reprint in _Meaning_of_Truth_. The review referred to is reprinted below, pp. 244-265, under the title "Humanism and Truth Once More." ED.]

consist in a relation between our experiences

and something archetypal or trans-experiential.

Should we ever reach absolutely terminal

experiences, experiences in which we all agreed,

which were superseded by no revised continuations,

these would not be _true_, they would be

_real_, they would simply _be_, and be indeed the

angles, corners, and linchpins of all reality, on

which the truth of everything else would be

stayed. Only such _other_ thins as led to these

by satisfactory conjunctions would be 'true.'

Satisfactory connection of some sort with such

termini is all that the word 'truth' means.

On the common-sense stage of thought sense-

presentations serve as such termini. our ideas

and concepts and scientific theories pass for

true only so far as they harmoniously lead back

to the world of sense.

I hope that many humanists will endorse

this attempt of mine to trace the more essential

features of that way of viewing things. I

feel almost certain that Messrs. Dewey and

205

Schiller will do so. If the attackers will also

take some slight account of it, it may be that

discussion will be a little less wide of the mark

than it has hitherto been.